
The Order of Things
An Archaeology of Human Sciences
Categories
Nonfiction, Psychology, Philosophy, Science, History, Anthropology, Sociology, Academic, Theory, France
Content Type
Book
Binding
Paperback
Year
1994
Publisher
Vintage
Language
English
ASIN
0679753354
ISBN
0679753354
ISBN13
9780679753353
File Download
PDF | EPUB
The Order of Things Plot Summary
Introduction
Western thought has undergone profound transformations that cannot be explained through traditional narratives of scientific progress or the gradual accumulation of knowledge. These transformations represent fundamental ruptures in the very conditions that make knowledge possible—what Michel Foucault terms "epistemes." Rather than seeing intellectual history as a continuous development of ideas, Foucault's archaeological method reveals discontinuities where entirely new configurations of knowledge emerge, making certain questions possible while rendering others unthinkable. The archaeological approach challenges our most basic assumptions about the history of ideas by demonstrating that concepts we take as natural or universal—like "man," "life," or "language"—are in fact historically contingent constructions that emerged at specific moments. By excavating these epistemic foundations, we gain critical distance from our own ways of thinking and can recognize their historical specificity. This perspective invites us to question not just what we know, but how knowledge itself is structured and what objects can appear within its domain—a radical reframing that opens new possibilities for understanding both our intellectual past and present.
Chapter 1: Foucault's Archaeological Method: Beyond Traditional History of Ideas
Foucault's archaeological method represents a radical departure from traditional intellectual history. Rather than tracing the linear development of ideas through time, archaeology examines the underlying structures—what Foucault terms "epistemes"—that govern what counts as knowledge in a given historical period. These epistemes are not conscious rules or methodologies but the unspoken conditions that determine what questions can be asked and what statements can be considered true. The archaeological approach reveals that Western thought has undergone fundamental discontinuities rather than smooth evolutions. The most significant of these ruptures occurred at the end of the 18th century, marking the transition from the Classical to the modern episteme. This transformation was not simply a matter of new discoveries or theories, but a complete reconfiguration of the space of knowledge itself. What changed was not merely what we know, but how knowledge itself is structured and what objects can appear within its domain. Unlike conventional historical analysis that seeks continuities and influences between thinkers, archaeology examines the discursive formations that make certain types of statements possible in the first place. It looks at the "positive unconscious" of knowledge—the unspoken rules that determine what counts as a valid scientific statement in a given era. These rules operate below the level of conscious methodological choices or theoretical frameworks. The archaeological method also differs from traditional intellectual history in its treatment of the subject. Rather than seeing ideas as the products of individual genius or intention, Foucault examines how subjectivity itself is constituted within specific discursive practices. The thinking subject is not the origin of discourse but is itself an effect of discursive formations. This represents a decisive break with phenomenological approaches that take the experiencing subject as their starting point. By focusing on these epistemic ruptures, archaeology reveals that concepts we take as natural or universal—like "man," "life," or "language"—are in fact historically contingent constructions that emerged at specific moments. Before the modern age, "man" as we understand the concept today simply did not exist as an object of knowledge. This insight challenges our most basic assumptions about the continuity of human self-understanding throughout history.
Chapter 2: The Classical Episteme: Representation as the Foundation of Knowledge
The Classical age (roughly 1650-1800) was governed by a distinctive epistemic configuration centered on representation. Knowledge was understood as the ordering of representations in a continuous, tabular space. This ordering took the form of a mathesis—a universal science of measurement and order—that served as the foundation for all knowledge. Within this framework, to know meant to establish identities and differences, to classify, and to create taxonomies. Language played a crucial role in this epistemic arrangement. In the Classical age, words and things were bound together in a transparent system of representation. Language was not understood as having its own density or historicity but functioned as a neutral medium that allowed representations to be analyzed and ordered. The sign was conceived as a binary structure linking a signifier directly to a signified without any intervening thickness or opacity. This binary conception replaced the Renaissance notion of resemblance, where signs participated in the things they signified through similarity. The Classical episteme manifested itself across diverse domains of knowledge. In natural history, living beings were classified according to their visible features arranged in taxonomic tables. The naturalist's task was not to penetrate the depths of organisms but to describe their visible surfaces and arrange them in ordered series. Similarly, in the analysis of wealth, economists organized economic phenomena according to their representational values in exchange. And in general grammar, language was analyzed as a system for representing thoughts through conventional signs. What unified these seemingly disparate domains was their common epistemological structure: all operated within the space of representation and followed the same principles of ordering. Knowledge was conceived as a table where identities and differences could be systematically arranged. This tabular conception of knowledge explains the Classical preoccupation with classification, taxonomy, and the creation of encyclopedic systems that could encompass all possible knowledge. The Classical episteme was also characterized by its treatment of time. Rather than seeing time as a fundamental dimension of being, Classical thought treated temporality as a secondary feature—merely the space in which representations unfolded. History was understood not as a force with its own laws but as the chronicle of representations succeeding one another. This explains why evolutionary thinking was impossible within the Classical framework, despite the fact that Classical naturalists were aware of similarities between species.
Chapter 3: The Birth of Modern Sciences: Life, Labor, and Language
The epistemic rupture at the end of the 18th century transformed the very foundations of knowledge, giving birth to entirely new sciences. This transformation is most clearly visible in the emergence of biology, political economy, and philology—sciences that could not exist within the Classical episteme. What made these new sciences possible was not simply the accumulation of new facts or the refinement of methods, but a fundamental reconfiguration of the epistemic space itself. In the domain of living beings, the taxonomic approach of natural history gave way to the study of organic structures and functions. Cuvier's comparative anatomy revealed that the visible features of organisms were subordinate to their internal functional organization. Living beings were no longer understood as bearers of visible characteristics that could be arranged in a continuous table, but as integrated systems whose parts were functionally related to one another. This shift made possible the emergence of biology as a science concerned with life itself rather than with the classification of visible forms. A parallel transformation occurred in the study of wealth. Classical economic thought had analyzed wealth in terms of representation—how objects of need represented one another in exchange. Ricardo fundamentally altered this approach by establishing labor as the source of value. Value was no longer understood as a function of exchange but as the product of labor expended in production. This shift made possible the emergence of political economy as a science concerned with the laws of production rather than the representation of wealth in exchange. In the study of language, a similar transformation took place. Classical general grammar had analyzed language as a system for representing thoughts. The new science of philology, exemplified by the work of Bopp and Grimm, approached languages as historical entities with their own internal laws of transformation. Languages were no longer understood as more or less perfect systems of representation but as organic structures that developed according to regular patterns independent of human intention. What unified these transformations was a common epistemological shift: in each case, the object of study retreated from the space of representation into its own autonomous domain with its own internal laws. Life, labor, and language emerged as dense, opaque realities that could not be reduced to representation. This retreat created the conditions for new sciences concerned not with the ordering of representations but with the analysis of organic structures, productive forces, and linguistic systems. This epistemological transformation also introduced a new dimension into Western thought: historicity. Life, labor, and language were now understood not as static entities but as historical realities that developed according to their own internal dynamics. This historicization of knowledge made possible new forms of analysis concerned with origins, development, and transformation—analyses that were unthinkable within the Classical episteme.
Chapter 4: Man as Subject and Object: The Empirico-Transcendental Doublet
The epistemic rupture at the end of the 18th century created a new configuration of knowledge in which "man" emerged simultaneously as both the subject who knows and an object to be known. This double position—what Foucault calls the "empirico-transcendental doublet"—defines the modern episteme and gives rise to the human sciences. Man appears as a finite being who must seek the conditions of his own knowledge within his empirical limitations. This new epistemic arrangement emerged from the dissolution of representation as the unifying field of knowledge. When representation could no longer serve as the transparent medium connecting words and things, man appeared in the resulting gap—as both the source of representations and that which is represented. Knowledge was no longer conceived as the ordering of representations in a table but as the investigation of objects that exist outside representation and according to their own laws. The collapse of the Classical episteme was visible across multiple domains. In biology, Cuvier showed that living beings must be understood not through their visible surfaces but through their functional organization and internal structures. In economics, Ricardo demonstrated that labor, not representation, was the source of value. In philology, languages were analyzed not as systems of representation but as historical entities with their own internal laws of transformation. In each case, the object of study retreated from the space of representation into its own autonomous domain. This retreat of objects from representation created a new problem: how could knowledge of these objects be possible? The answer was found in the figure of man as a finite being who could know these objects precisely because he was constituted by the same forces that produced them. As a living, laboring, speaking being, man could know life, labor, and language. But this created a paradoxical situation: man became both the foundation of all knowledge and an object among others—both transcendental subject and empirical object. The birth of man as an epistemic figure also marked the emergence of a new relationship to finitude. In Classical thought, human finitude was understood negatively—as a limitation that prevented perfect knowledge. In modern thought, finitude became positive and constitutive—the very condition that makes knowledge possible. Man's limitations were no longer obstacles to overcome but the foundation of all possible understanding.
Chapter 5: The Analytic of Finitude: Modern Thought's Fundamental Structure
The modern episteme is fundamentally structured around what Foucault terms the "analytic of finitude." This refers to the paradoxical attempt to derive the conditions of knowledge from the very limitations of human existence. Unlike Classical thought, which measured human finitude against the infinite (God, eternal truths), modern thought seeks to understand finitude on its own terms—as both the empirical condition and transcendental foundation of knowledge. This analytic takes several forms, each characterized by a peculiar doubling structure. First is the empirico-transcendental doublet, where man appears simultaneously as an object of empirical knowledge (studied by biology, economics, philology) and as the transcendental subject who makes that knowledge possible. This creates an unstable oscillation between empirical content and transcendental foundation that can never be resolved within the modern episteme. A second doubling occurs in the relation between the cogito and the unthought. Unlike Descartes' transparent self-consciousness, the modern cogito is haunted by an unthought dimension—unconscious processes, bodily mechanisms, historical determinations—that it can never fully illuminate. Modern thought is thus characterized by the endless task of bringing the unthought into consciousness, a project that can never be completed because the unthought is constitutive of thought itself. The third doubling concerns the retreat and return of the origin. Modern thought is obsessed with origins—the origin of life, of language, of society—yet these origins constantly recede from view. Man discovers that he is always already separated from his origins by forces that precede his consciousness. Yet paradoxically, as a finite being, man is also supposed to be the foundation that makes the search for origins possible. These three doublings create the distinctive character of modern thought: its constant oscillation between the empirical and the transcendental, the conscious and the unconscious, the historical and the originary. This oscillation generates the endless questioning that characterizes modern philosophy and the human sciences. Unlike Classical thought, which sought to establish a stable order of representations, modern thought is driven by the impossible task of reconciling man's position as both subject and object of knowledge. The analytic of finitude also explains the emergence of new philosophical projects in the 19th century. Phenomenology, Marxism, and psychoanalysis can all be understood as attempts to resolve the paradoxes of the modern episteme—to reconcile the empirical and the transcendental, to illuminate the unthought, or to recover lost origins. Yet these projects remain trapped within the epistemic configuration they seek to overcome.
Chapter 6: Human Sciences and Their Methodological Limitations
The human sciences occupy a peculiar and precarious position within the modern episteme. They are neither purely empirical sciences like biology or economics, nor transcendental investigations like Kantian philosophy. Instead, they exist in an intermediate space, attempting to bridge the gap between empirical contents and transcendental foundations that defines the modern episteme. What distinguishes the human sciences is not their object—man—but their distinctive epistemological configuration. They take as their domain the representations through which human beings relate to their lives, their labor, and their language. Unlike biology, economics, or linguistics, which study life, labor, and language in their positivity, the human sciences study how these realities are represented in human consciousness and behavior. This peculiar position explains the methodological instability of the human sciences. They constantly oscillate between different models borrowed from the empirical sciences. Psychology, sociology, and cultural analysis have variously adopted biological models (focusing on functions and norms), economic models (focusing on conflicts and rules), or linguistic models (focusing on meaning and systems). These borrowings are not accidental but reflect the fundamental structure of the modern episteme. The human sciences are also characterized by their ambiguous relationship to representation. While the empirical sciences broke free from the Classical space of representation to study objects in their autonomous reality, the human sciences remained tied to representation as both their object and their method. They study how human beings represent their existence to themselves, yet they must also represent these representations in their own discourse. This circular relationship to representation creates distinctive methodological problems. The human sciences are constantly caught between the attempt to achieve scientific objectivity and the recognition that their own discourse is implicated in the representations they study. This explains their perpetual methodological crises and their oscillation between claims to scientific status and hermeneutic approaches that emphasize interpretation over explanation. The precarious status of the human sciences also stems from their relationship to finitude. Unlike the empirical sciences, which study objects in their positivity, the human sciences constantly confront the limits of human existence—the fact that man is a finite being trying to understand his own finitude. This creates a peculiar doubling where the human sciences must constantly reflect on their own conditions of possibility even as they attempt to produce positive knowledge.
Chapter 7: The Return of Language and the Possible End of Man
The modern episteme, defined by the figure of man as both subject and object of knowledge, may be approaching its end. This potential transformation is signaled by the "return of language" in contemporary thought—a renewed attention to language not as a transparent medium of representation but as an autonomous reality with its own being and historicity. This return is visible in diverse domains: in literature (Mallarmé, Blanchot), philosophy (Nietzsche, Heidegger), and the human sciences themselves (structural linguistics, discourse analysis). This renewed focus on language challenges the very foundations of the modern episteme. If language is not simply a tool used by a sovereign subject but a reality that precedes and constitutes subjectivity, then "man" as conceived in modern thought—the empirico-transcendental doublet—becomes problematic. The speaking subject appears not as the origin of discourse but as an effect produced within discourse. As Nietzsche suggested, we should ask not what man is but who speaks. The return of language also disrupts the relationship between words and things that defined the modern episteme. Language no longer appears as a transparent medium connecting a knowing subject to known objects but as an opaque reality that follows its own laws. This opacity challenges the modern project of grounding knowledge in human subjectivity. If language has its own being independent of human intentions, then knowledge cannot be secured by reference to a transcendental subject. This transformation is particularly evident in literature, where writers have explored language as an autonomous force that exceeds the control of the speaking subject. Their work reveals language not as a means of expression but as an experience of the limits of subjectivity—of death, absence, and the dissolution of the self. Literature thus becomes a privileged site for experiencing the possible end of "man" as conceived in modern thought. The emergence of formalized languages in mathematics and logic points in a similar direction. These languages attempt to eliminate the ambiguities of natural language and establish systems of notation that operate according to explicit rules. In doing so, they challenge the assumption that language is fundamentally expressive of human experience and point instead to its formal, rule-governed character. These developments suggest that we may be witnessing the dissolution of the modern episteme and the figure of "man" that defined it. Just as the Classical episteme gave way to the modern at the end of the 18th century, so the modern episteme may be giving way to a new configuration of knowledge. This would not mean the disappearance of human beings but the end of a particular way of conceptualizing human existence—as an empirico-transcendental doublet caught between being a subject of knowledge and an object to be known.
Summary
The archaeological analysis reveals that what we take as natural or inevitable ways of thinking are in fact historically contingent configurations of knowledge. The modern conception of "man" as both subject and object of knowledge emerged from a specific epistemic rupture at the end of the 18th century and may be approaching its end. This perspective challenges us to recognize the historical contingency of our most basic categories and concepts, including our understanding of ourselves as human beings. The fundamental insight that emerges from this archaeological excavation is that thinking itself has a history—not just the content of thought but its very form and possibility. What can be thought, questioned, or known in a given period depends on underlying epistemic structures that are largely invisible to those who operate within them. By making these structures visible, archaeological analysis creates the possibility of thinking differently—of stepping outside our current epistemic constraints to imagine alternative ways of organizing knowledge and understanding human existence.
Best Quote
“This book first arose out of a passage in [Jorge Luis] Borges, out of the laughter that shattered, as I read the passage, all the familiar landmarks of my thought—our thought that bears the stamp of our age and our geography—breaking up all the ordered surfaces and all the planes with which we are accustomed to tame the wild profusion of existing things, and continuing long afterwards to disturb and threaten with collapse our age-old distinction between the Same and the Other. This passage quotes a ‘certain Chinese encyclopaedia’ in which it is written that ‘animals are divided into: (a) belonging to the Emperor, (b) embalmed, (c) tame, (d) suckling pigs, (e) sirens, (f) fabulous, (g) stray dogs, (h) included in the present classification, (i) frenzied, (j) innumerable, (k) drawn with a very fine camelhair brush, (l) et cetera, (m) having just broken the water pitcher, (n) that from a long way off look like flies’. In the wonderment of this taxonomy, the thing we apprehend in one great leap, the thing that, by means of the fable, is demonstrated as the exotic charm of another system of thought, is the limitation of our own, the stark impossibility of thinking that.” ― Michel Foucault, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences
Review Summary
Strengths: The book is described as "stunningly interesting" and "erudite," indicating its intellectual depth and engaging nature. The reviewer appreciates the book's exploration of how categorization reflects human nature and values the insightful interpretation of Velasquez's "Las Meninas."\nWeaknesses: The review suggests that some arguments in the book are complex and require further contemplation to fully understand, indicating that it may be challenging for some readers.\nOverall Sentiment: Enthusiastic\nKey Takeaway: The book offers a profound exploration of human categorization and its implications, using historical and artistic references to illustrate its points. It is intellectually stimulating but may require careful consideration to grasp all its arguments fully.
Trending Books
Download PDF & EPUB
To save this Black List summary for later, download the free PDF and EPUB. You can print it out, or read offline at your convenience.

The Order of Things
By Michel Foucault