
Either/Or
A Fragment of Life
Categories
Nonfiction, Psychology, Philosophy, Religion, Classics, Literature, Theology, Scandinavian Literature, 19th Century, Danish
Content Type
Book
Binding
Paperback
Year
1992
Publisher
Penguin Classics
Language
English
File Download
PDF | EPUB
Either/Or Plot Summary
Introduction
Human existence presents us with a fundamental choice between two radically different ways of living. We can either embrace an aesthetic lifestyle focused on pleasure, immediacy, and the avoidance of commitment, or we can choose an ethical existence grounded in responsibility, continuity, and meaningful engagement with others. This dichotomy represents not merely different preferences but fundamentally incompatible orientations toward life itself. The aesthetic individual lives in the moment, pursuing pleasure and avoiding pain, while the ethical person establishes continuity through commitment and finds meaning in responsibility rather than in freedom from obligation. The significance of this framework lies in its challenge to conventional thinking about freedom and happiness. Modern culture often equates freedom with keeping options open and avoiding definitive choices. Yet this approach paradoxically leads to a fragmented existence lacking coherence and depth. By examining the inherent limitations of aesthetic living and contrasting it with the possibilities offered by ethical existence, we gain insight into contemporary struggles with meaning, identity, and commitment. The dialectical method employed illuminates how these two modes of existence relate to fundamental human concerns: our relationship to time, to others, and ultimately to ourselves as beings capable of choice and responsibility.
Chapter 1: The Fundamental Dichotomy: Two Modes of Existence
Human existence unfolds between two fundamentally different possibilities: the aesthetic and the ethical. These represent not merely different lifestyles or preferences but distinct ways of relating to oneself and to existence as a whole. The aesthetic life is characterized by immediacy, pleasure-seeking, and avoidance of commitment. It focuses on the moment, pursuing what is interesting, pleasurable, or novel without concern for continuity or coherence. The ethical life, by contrast, centers on choice, commitment, and responsibility. It establishes continuity through time and finds meaning in obligations freely embraced rather than in freedom from obligation. The aesthetic individual lives primarily in relation to external circumstances, allowing moods, desires, and opportunities to determine their actions. They may appear active in their pursuit of pleasure or interesting experiences, but this activity lacks direction beyond the satisfaction of immediate desires. The aesthete refuses to make definitive choices that would limit possibilities, preferring to remain in a state of perpetual openness. This approach manifests across a spectrum from crude hedonism to sophisticated intellectual or artistic pursuits, but all forms share the fundamental characteristic of avoiding commitment and the responsibility it entails. The ethical individual, conversely, actively chooses themselves and their life path. This choice is not merely selecting among external options but choosing oneself absolutely—accepting responsibility for who one is and actively shaping who one becomes. Through this choice, the ethical person establishes continuity between past, present, and future, integrating disparate experiences into a coherent narrative of selfhood. They find freedom not in avoiding commitment but in embracing it as the expression of their authentic self. This dichotomy manifests in concrete ways across various domains of life. In relationships, the aesthetic approach treats others as sources of pleasure or interest, maintaining distance to preserve freedom. The ethical approach embraces commitment to others, finding deeper satisfaction in enduring bonds than in novel encounters. In work, the aesthetic individual seeks primarily entertainment or status, while the ethical person finds meaning in contributing to something beyond themselves. In relation to time, the aesthete tries to maximize the intensity of moments, while the ethical individual develops through time, finding value in continuity and development. The distinction between these modes of existence cannot be resolved through theoretical reflection alone. No logical argument can compel the movement from aesthetic to ethical existence because the very standards of judgment differ between them. What appears as freedom to the aesthete seems like emptiness to the ethical person; what the ethical individual experiences as meaningful commitment appears as burdensome limitation to the aesthete. This incommensurability means that the transition between them requires not reasoning but choice—a leap that transforms the very framework within which one understands existence. The significance of this dichotomy extends beyond individual psychology to fundamental questions about human existence. It challenges both deterministic views that deny human freedom and relativistic positions that avoid substantive commitments. Against both, it affirms that human beings must choose themselves and their mode of existence, and that this choice has consequences for the kind of self one becomes. Neither drifting unreflectively through life nor abstractly contemplating it constitutes authentic existence; one must actively choose and thereby constitute oneself as a specific kind of being.
Chapter 2: Aesthetic Life: Immediacy, Pleasure, and Despair
The aesthetic life represents an existence devoted to immediacy, where one lives primarily in and for the moment without reflection on continuity or deeper meaning. This mode of existence manifests across a spectrum from crude sensuality to refined intellectual or artistic pursuits. At its most basic level, the aesthetic life focuses on physical pleasure, comfort, and the satisfaction of immediate desires. More sophisticated forms might center on romantic love, artistic creation, or intellectual stimulation. What unites these diverse expressions is their common foundation in immediacy and their avoidance of definitive choice and commitment. The aesthetic individual relates to time in a distinctive way, seeking to maximize the intensity of each moment rather than establishing continuity between moments. This creates a paradoxical relationship to boredom—the aesthete considers boredom the root of all evil and organizes existence around its avoidance, yet inevitably falls prey to it as pleasures lose their novelty. This leads to increasingly desperate strategies of "rotation," where one constantly varies activities, relationships, or interests to maintain stimulation. Despite these efforts, boredom returns with greater intensity, revealing a fundamental emptiness at the heart of aesthetic existence. A defining characteristic of aesthetic life is its essential passivity. Despite apparent activity in pursuing pleasures or interests, the aesthetic individual allows themselves to be determined by external circumstances, moods, and desires rather than actively shaping their existence through choice. This passivity manifests in a tendency to view oneself as a spectator rather than a participant in one's own life, observing and experiencing without taking responsibility. The aesthete may develop remarkable insight into human psychology and social dynamics while remaining fundamentally detached from genuine engagement with others or commitment to values beyond momentary interest. The most sophisticated form of aesthetic existence manifests as ironic detachment. The ironic individual maintains distance from all commitments, viewing everything from a position of superior amusement. This stance provides protection from disappointment and failure by refusing to take anything, including oneself, entirely seriously. Yet this very protection becomes a prison, preventing genuine connection with others and authentic engagement with life. The ironic individual gains apparent freedom from all constraints but loses the possibility of finding meaning through commitment. Aesthetic existence ultimately leads to despair, though this despair may remain hidden beneath a veneer of pleasure-seeking or intellectual sophistication. This despair emerges from the fundamental emptiness of a life without continuity or commitment. Without stable values or enduring relationships, nothing has lasting significance; everything becomes interchangeable and ultimately meaningless. The aesthetic individual may attempt to conceal this despair through intensified pursuit of pleasure, through ironic detachment, or through intellectual analysis, but these strategies merely mask rather than resolve the underlying condition. This despair, however, contains the potential for transformation. When the aesthetic individual recognizes the emptiness of their existence—when they confront the impossibility of finding lasting satisfaction through immediacy alone—the possibility of ethical existence emerges. The very experience of despair can become the catalyst for a leap into a different mode of being, one based not on immediacy and pleasure but on choice, commitment, and responsibility. This transition cannot occur through gradual development but requires a decisive break with aesthetic values and the embrace of an entirely different relationship to existence.
Chapter 3: Ethical Existence: Commitment, Continuity, and Meaning
The ethical life represents a fundamental alternative to aesthetic existence through its emphasis on choice and commitment. While the aesthete avoids definitive choices to preserve possibility, the ethical individual actively chooses and thereby establishes continuity and coherence in life. This choice is not primarily about specific external actions but about choosing oneself in an absolute sense—accepting responsibility for one's existence and committing to the development of one's essential humanity. Through this choice, the scattered moments of aesthetic existence are gathered into a coherent whole, and the individual establishes continuity between past, present, and future. Central to ethical existence is the concept of duty, but not as an external imposition that constrains freedom. Rather, duty emerges from within as an expression of one's authentic selfhood. The ethical individual recognizes universal human obligations not as alien commands but as expressions of their own deeper nature. This internalization of duty transforms what might otherwise be experienced as limitation into a form of self-expression and freedom. The ethical person does not say "I must do this despite myself" but rather "I must do this because this is who I truly am." The ethical life resolves the despair inherent in aesthetic existence by providing what the latter fundamentally lacks: meaning that transcends momentary satisfaction. Through commitment to universal human values and particular relationships, the ethical individual participates in something larger than themselves without losing their individuality. This participation grants significance to actions beyond their immediate consequences or pleasurable qualities. The ethical person finds joy not despite commitment but through it—not in keeping all options open but in binding themselves to what they recognize as truly valuable. Ethical existence transforms the experience of time itself. While the aesthete experiences time as a burden to be filled with diversion or as a series of disconnected moments, the ethical individual experiences time as the medium for developing and expressing selfhood. Each moment acquires significance through its connection to an ongoing project of becoming. The past is not merely remembered but actively integrated into a coherent narrative; the future is not merely anticipated but shaped through present commitments. This temporal integration creates a sense of continuity that transcends the fluctuations of mood and circumstance. The ethical perspective recognizes that genuine development requires patience and persistence. Unlike aesthetic transformation, which occurs through sudden inspiration or dramatic conversion, ethical growth unfolds gradually through consistent effort. This process lacks the spectacular quality of aesthetic experience but possesses greater depth and substance. The ethical individual does not seek to arrest time or escape its passage but to give it meaning through faithful commitment to chosen values and relationships. Through ethical commitment, the individual establishes a relationship to the universal within particular circumstances. The ethical person does not abandon individuality for abstract universality but expresses universal human values through their unique situation and personality. This creates a dialectical relationship between the universal and particular aspects of selfhood—the ethical individual simultaneously chooses humanity in general and their particular historical existence. This resolves the contradiction between viewing oneself as merely a specimen of humanity and as absolutely unique.
Chapter 4: Marriage as the Paradigm of Ethical Commitment
Marriage represents the paradigmatic example of the transition from aesthetic to ethical existence. First love, in its immediate romantic form, belongs to the aesthetic sphere—it is characterized by passion, idealization, and a sense of destiny beyond choice. Marriage transforms this immediate relationship into an ethical commitment that endures through time and changing circumstances. This transformation does not negate the aesthetic elements of love but integrates them into a more substantial and enduring form. The aesthetic view sees marriage as the death of love, a descent from romantic heights into bourgeois routine. From this perspective, the excitement of first love inevitably fades, leaving only habit and obligation. The ethical view, by contrast, recognizes that marriage does not destroy love but fulfills it by giving it continuity and substance. The ethical individual does not abandon romantic love but incorporates it into a deeper and more enduring relationship. What appears as the loss of immediacy actually becomes the condition for a richer and more developed form of love. Marriage involves a decisive choice that transforms the nature of love. While first love appears as something that simply happens to individuals, marriage represents a deliberate commitment to maintain and develop love through time. This commitment does not diminish love's intensity but gives it a foundation that can withstand life's challenges and changes. The married couple does not merely endure time but actively uses it to build a love that becomes increasingly particular and irreplaceable. Their shared history creates a depth of connection impossible in relationships based solely on immediate attraction. The ethical view of marriage rejects both romantic idealization and cynical disillusionment. It acknowledges the reality of difficulties and conflicts while maintaining faith in love's capacity to overcome them. Unlike aesthetic love, which flourishes only under favorable conditions, ethical love develops strength through confronting and resolving obstacles. The ethical individual recognizes that love requires not just passion but patience, not just attraction but active care and attention. This realistic yet hopeful approach allows love to mature without losing its essential character. Marriage exemplifies how ethical commitment transforms not only relationships but the individuals within them. Through marriage, partners do not simply maintain a connection but develop new dimensions of selfhood impossible in isolation or temporary relationships. They learn to see themselves through the eyes of another who knows them deeply, to recognize both their limitations and possibilities more clearly. This mutual recognition creates the conditions for genuine growth and self-knowledge impossible in the aesthetic sphere, where relationships remain superficial and transient. The ethical significance of marriage extends beyond the relationship between spouses to encompass broader human connections. Through marriage, individuals establish connections to family, community, and future generations. These connections provide context and meaning for individual existence, countering the isolation that characterizes aesthetic life. The married person does not lose individuality but finds it more fully expressed through participation in these wider circles of relationship. Marriage thus becomes not just a private arrangement but a way of participating in and contributing to human community across time.
Chapter 5: Self-Choice: The Path to Authentic Selfhood
The concept of choosing oneself stands at the center of the transition from aesthetic to ethical existence. This choice differs fundamentally from ordinary choices between external alternatives. When one chooses oneself, the choice and its object coincide—the choosing self and the chosen self are identical. This paradoxical structure makes self-choice uniquely transformative; through it, one does not merely select among pre-existing possibilities but actively constitutes oneself as a specific kind of being. Self-choice involves accepting oneself in one's concrete particularity while simultaneously recognizing a responsibility for who one becomes. The individual acknowledges all the contingent factors that have shaped them—their temperament, talents, social position, personal history—yet refuses to be merely determined by these factors. In choosing oneself, one takes possession of these givens and transforms them from mere facts into tasks and possibilities. What was received passively is actively appropriated and integrated into a coherent self-understanding. This choice has a crucial temporal dimension. In choosing oneself, one establishes continuity between past, present, and future. The past is not disowned but reinterpreted and incorporated into an ongoing narrative of selfhood. The ethical individual "repents" the past not merely as something regrettable but as something for which one assumes responsibility even when it resulted from ignorance or immaturity. This retrospective responsibility transforms the meaning of the past by integrating it into a coherent narrative of selfhood that extends into the future. Authentic selfhood emerges through this process of self-choice and its subsequent elaboration in concrete life choices. The authentic self is not an abstract universal but a particular individual who expresses universal human values in a unique way. It is neither a mere product of circumstances nor a pure self-creation but rather a synthesis that acknowledges both determination and freedom. The authentic individual recognizes both their boundedness to specific conditions and their transcendence of those conditions through conscious choice. The path to authentic selfhood involves a paradoxical combination of isolation and connection. The moment of choice represents a radical isolation—no one can choose for another, and the choice cannot be derived from any external authority or standard. Yet what is chosen includes precisely one's relationships and commitments to others. The authentic self is not an isolated monad but a center of relationships chosen and affirmed as constitutive of who one is. This understanding of selfhood challenges both deterministic views that reduce the self to a product of causal factors and voluntaristic conceptions that imagine a self created ex nihilo through sheer will. Instead, it offers a nuanced account of how freedom operates within necessity, how choice works with given conditions, and how individuality relates to universality. The authentic self emerges not by escaping determination but by actively relating to it—not by creating itself from nothing but by choosing itself from among the concrete possibilities that constitute its situation.
Chapter 6: The Religious Dimension: Beyond Ethics
The distinction between aesthetic and ethical existence provides a powerful framework for understanding human life, but it is not the complete picture. Beyond both modes lies a religious dimension that both builds upon and transcends the ethical. This religious stage does not negate ethical commitments but rather places them in relation to something absolute—the individual's relationship to God or the eternal. This relationship transforms the meaning of ethical duties without abolishing them. The movement to the religious begins with the recognition of the limits of ethical existence. Even the most committed ethical individual eventually encounters situations where ethical demands conflict or where human capabilities fall short of ethical ideals. This creates a crisis that cannot be resolved within the ethical framework itself. The individual discovers that despite their sincere commitment to universal human values, they repeatedly fail to fully embody these values. This recognition of one's fundamental inadequacy before the ethical ideal creates a profound sense of guilt that points beyond ethics toward a religious relationship. In the religious dimension, the individual stands in an absolute relationship to the absolute. This relationship is characterized by a paradoxical combination of absolute demand and absolute forgiveness. The religious individual recognizes themselves as "always in the wrong before God"—not as a degrading self-condemnation but as an acknowledgment of the infinite qualitative difference between human and divine. This recognition becomes not a source of despair but of profound joy, as it simultaneously affirms both human limitation and divine grace. The religious stage introduces concepts that transcend ethical categories. Sin replaces moral failure as the fundamental problem, representing not just violation of ethical norms but a condition of the entire self in relation to God. Similarly, forgiveness replaces moral improvement as the solution, representing not gradual ethical development but a transformative relationship to transcendence that gives new meaning to finite existence. These religious categories do not invalidate ethical distinctions between good and evil but place them within a broader framework that acknowledges their ultimate insufficiency. The paradigmatic religious figure is not the moral hero who perfectly embodies ethical ideals but the "knight of faith" who maintains absolute commitment to both the finite and the infinite simultaneously. This figure lives fully in the world of ethical relationships and responsibilities while maintaining an absolute relationship to the absolute that relativizes all finite concerns without diminishing their importance. This paradoxical position cannot be understood through philosophical categories but must be lived as an existential reality. The movement from despair to faith represents the highest possibility of human existence. Faith emerges as a response to the deeper despair that comes from recognizing the limitations of ethical striving. Rather than abandoning ethical commitment, faith transforms its meaning by relating the finite to the infinite. The religious individual continues to fulfill ethical duties but no longer expects these actions to produce self-justification or absolute meaning. Instead, meaning comes from relating to the absolute paradoxically—through a relationship that acknowledges the infinite qualitative difference between human and divine while affirming their connection.
Chapter 7: Kierkegaard's Challenge to Modern Philosophy
The framework of either/or represents a fundamental challenge to Hegelian philosophy and its method of dialectical mediation. While Hegel sought to overcome contradictions by synthesizing opposing terms into higher unities, this approach insists on the irreducible nature of certain existential dilemmas. Some choices cannot be mediated or reconciled through conceptual thinking; they demand decision rather than reflection, commitment rather than contemplation. This challenge extends beyond Hegel to modern philosophy more generally, questioning its emphasis on abstract, objective knowledge over subjective, existential truth. Abstract thinking fails precisely where it matters most—in guiding actual human lives. It can analyze ethical principles in general but cannot tell a particular individual what they should do in their concrete situation. It can contemplate the nature of selfhood as a concept but cannot help someone become a self. It can reflect on time as an abstract category but cannot show how to live meaningfully in time. These limitations reveal not merely practical difficulties but a fundamental inadequacy in the approach itself when applied to existential questions. The alternative to abstract thinking is not irrationalism but a different kind of thinking that acknowledges its own embeddedness in existence. This existential thinking recognizes that the thinker is not a detached observer but a participant in what is thought. It understands that certain truths can only be approached through commitment rather than contemplation, and that some realities can only be known by being lived rather than merely conceived. This mode of thinking does not abandon rigor or clarity but redirects them toward illuminating existence rather than constructing systems. The critique extends to the Hegelian notion of world-historical development, which subsumes individual existence under the movement of universal Spirit. Against this view stands the insistence that ethical and religious truth cannot be mediated through historical processes or conceptual developments. The individual stands alone before the absolute demands of ethics and faith, and no philosophical system can relieve them of the burden of choice or the anxiety of freedom. This position affirms the irreducible significance of individual existence against all attempts to dissolve it into abstract universality. This challenge to philosophy extends to its communication methods. If existential truth cannot be adequately captured in abstract concepts, then philosophical communication must find ways to address the whole person rather than merely the intellect. This explains the use of literary devices, pseudonyms, and indirect communication—these methods respect the reader's freedom and the nature of existential truth as something that must be appropriated personally rather than merely understood conceptually. True philosophical communication does not transmit finished results but creates conditions where individuals can discover truth for themselves. The significance of this critique lies in its defense of individual existence against the claims of abstract systems. It insists that no philosophical framework, however comprehensive, can relieve the individual of the burden and dignity of choice. It affirms that human beings are not merely instances of universal categories but unique existences that must forge their own relationship to truth through decision and commitment. This perspective offers a powerful alternative to both systematic philosophy and relativistic skepticism—a third way that acknowledges both the objective demands of truth and the subjective process through which it must be appropriated.
Summary
The fundamental insight illuminated through this dialectical exploration is that authentic human existence requires a conscious choice between fundamentally different ways of being. Neither drifting unreflectively through life nor abstractly contemplating it from a distance constitutes genuine living. We must choose ourselves—not just what we do but who we are—and this choice shapes everything that follows. The aesthetic life, with its pursuit of pleasure and avoidance of commitment, ultimately leads to despair despite its apparent freedom. The ethical life, embracing duty and continuity, offers a more substantial freedom through commitment rather than despite it. Beyond both lies the religious dimension, which does not negate ethics but transforms its meaning through relation to the absolute. The profound value of this framework lies in its rejection of both relativism and abstract moralism. It insists that meaningful existence requires commitment to values beyond subjective preference, while recognizing that such commitment must be freely chosen rather than externally imposed. This perspective speaks directly to contemporary struggles with choice, identity, and meaning. In an age overwhelmed by possibilities yet suspicious of absolute claims, it offers a path to selfhood that neither surrenders to arbitrary choice nor escapes into dogmatic certainty. The either/or confronts us with the inescapable task of becoming ourselves through choices that cannot be delegated or deferred—choices that constitute not just what we do but who we fundamentally are.
Best Quote
“I see it all perfectly; there are two possible situations — one can either do this or that. My honest opinion and my friendly advice is this: do it or do not do it — you will regret both.” ― Soren Kierkegaard, Either/Or: A Fragment of Life
Review Summary
Strengths: The review highlights the book's exploration of complex philosophical ideas, such as the dichotomy between different perspectives ("Eithers" and "Ors") and its engagement with postmodern themes. It appreciates the book's ability to deconstruct and challenge traditional notions of reality, drawing connections to both Kierkegaard and Hegel. Weaknesses: Not explicitly mentioned. Overall Sentiment: Mixed. The review acknowledges the book's intellectual depth and philosophical engagement but also suggests a sense of confusion or complexity that may not be easily accessible to all readers. Key Takeaway: The book is a thought-provoking exploration of philosophical dichotomies and postmodern ideas, drawing on the works of Kierkegaard and Hegel to question and deconstruct traditional ethical and metaphysical concepts.
Trending Books
Download PDF & EPUB
To save this Black List summary for later, download the free PDF and EPUB. You can print it out, or read offline at your convenience.

Either/Or
By Søren Kierkegaard