
Of Grammatology
The Foundations of Language, Writing, and Meaning
Categories
Nonfiction, Philosophy, Linguistics, Academic, Theory, Literary Criticism, 20th Century, France, Language, Criticism
Content Type
Book
Binding
Paperback
Year
1996
Publisher
Johns Hopkins University Press
Language
English
ASIN
0801858305
ISBN
0801858305
ISBN13
9780801858307
File Download
PDF | EPUB
Of Grammatology Plot Summary
Introduction
Western philosophy has traditionally privileged speech over writing, presence over absence, and identity over difference. This hierarchical structure, which Jacques Derrida terms "logocentrism," has dominated metaphysical thought from Plato to Heidegger. The fundamental challenge presented in this examination of writing is not merely to reverse these hierarchies but to expose how they undermine themselves from within. By analyzing the concept of writing beyond its conventional understanding as mere transcription of speech, we discover that the very qualities attributed to writing—absence, difference, spacing—are in fact constitutive of all language, including speech itself. The deconstruction of the speech-writing hierarchy reveals something more profound than a simple error in philosophical reasoning. It exposes the "metaphysics of presence" that structures Western thought—the assumption that being is presence and that truth must be fully present to consciousness. Through careful analysis of philosophical texts from Rousseau to Saussure, we follow a methodical unraveling of this metaphysical tradition, revealing how presence is always already inhabited by absence, how identity depends on difference, and how what appears most natural and immediate is constituted through processes of mediation and supplementation. This transformation in our understanding of language has profound implications for how we conceive of meaning, truth, subjectivity, and the very possibility of philosophy itself.
Chapter 1: The Metaphysics of Presence and Phonocentrism in Western Thought
Western philosophical tradition has consistently privileged speech over writing, establishing a hierarchy that reflects deeper metaphysical commitments. From Plato to Husserl, philosophers have valued speech for its apparent immediacy—the speaking subject seems present to what is said, creating an illusion that meaning is fully present in the spoken word. This privileging of speech, which Derrida terms "phonocentrism," is not merely a technical preference but a fundamental structure underpinning Western metaphysics. The metaphysics of presence assumes that being is presence, that truth is what can be fully present to consciousness. Speech appears to maintain an immediate connection between signifier and signified, between the speaking subject and meaning. The voice creates a circuit of self-presence where the speaker hears themselves speak in an apparently unmediated experience. Writing, by contrast, functions in the absence of both the writer and the intended recipient. It introduces distance, delay, and the possibility of misinterpretation. These qualities have led to writing being characterized throughout philosophical history as a dangerous supplement, a technical device that threatens the purity of meaning. This phonocentrism serves a specific function within metaphysical discourse. By privileging speech as the medium that provides immediate access to meaning, Western philosophy attempts to secure a foundation for knowledge that would escape the play of differences that constitutes language. The speaking subject, present to their own discourse, becomes the guarantor of meaning and truth. This foundation is precisely what deconstruction calls into question, showing how the very attempt to establish such a foundation necessarily relies on what it seeks to exclude. The privileging of speech over writing operates through a series of conceptual oppositions: presence/absence, immediate/mediated, natural/cultural, inside/outside. In each case, the first term is valued over the second, establishing hierarchies that structure philosophical thought. These oppositions are not merely descriptive but normative, carrying evaluative force that extends beyond philosophy to shape cultural attitudes and practices. The devaluation of writing parallels other hierarchical oppositions in Western thought, including those between soul and body, intelligible and sensible, masculine and feminine. By examining how philosophical texts consistently attempt to subordinate writing while simultaneously depending on it, deconstruction exposes the contradictions inherent in the metaphysics of presence. The very texts that proclaim the secondary nature of writing rely on writing to make their claims. This dependence reveals that the hierarchical opposition between speech and writing cannot be maintained. The qualities attributed to writing—absence, difference, iterability—turn out to be constitutive of all language, including speech itself. The critique of phonocentrism thus becomes not merely a specialized critique within linguistics or literary theory but a fundamental challenge to the conceptual foundations of Western thought.
Chapter 2: Writing Before Speech: Challenging Traditional Hierarchies
The traditional view positions writing as a secondary representation of speech, which itself represents thought. This double representation places writing at two removes from meaning or presence. However, a careful examination of the conditions that make signification possible reveals that what we call "writing"—understood as a system of differences, of traces—is not secondary but in fact conditions the possibility of speech itself. What Derrida terms "arche-writing" refers not simply to empirical writing systems but to the differential structure that makes all signification possible. This reversal of the traditional hierarchy between speech and writing does not simply elevate writing to a position of privilege previously occupied by speech. Rather, it demonstrates that the very qualities traditionally attributed to writing—absence, difference, spacing, iterability—are in fact constitutive of all language, including speech. Speech, no less than writing, functions through a system of differences rather than through immediate presence. The speaking subject is no more fully present to meaning than is the writing subject. Both speech and writing operate through the same fundamental structure of differentiation and deferral. The concept of arche-writing challenges the notion that there could ever be a pure, self-present meaning prior to its articulation in language. Meaning is always already caught up in the differential network of signs, always already inscribed. There is no meaning that precedes its inscription in a system of differences. This insight fundamentally challenges the metaphysical dream of a transcendental signified—a meaning that would stand outside the play of signifiers and anchor the entire system of language in a stable presence. By demonstrating that the characteristics traditionally attributed to writing—its functioning in absence, its iterability, its break with context—are in fact conditions for all signification, Derrida shows that the subordination of writing to speech cannot be maintained. The very possibility of meaning depends on the structural possibility of absence, repetition, and difference that writing exemplifies. Speech itself depends on these "writerly" characteristics to function as meaningful language. This reconceptualization of writing has profound implications for our understanding of language, meaning, and subjectivity. If there is no pure presence of meaning prior to its articulation in a system of differences, then the speaking subject cannot be understood as the sovereign origin of meaning. The subject itself is constituted through the differential play of language rather than standing outside it as its master. The dream of full self-presence, of consciousness immediately present to itself, is revealed as an illusion generated by the metaphysics of presence.
Chapter 3: Différance: The Movement That Produces Differences
Différance—a neologism that combines the French words for "to differ" and "to defer"—names the movement that produces differences, the non-originary origin of differences. It is neither a word nor a concept but rather the possibility of conceptuality, of the conceptual process and system in general. Crucially, différance is ungraspable within the logic of identity and presence that has dominated Western metaphysics. It cannot be made present, cannot be objectified, because it is precisely what makes presence and objectification possible. The "a" in différance, audibly indistinguishable from "difference" in French but visibly different in writing, points to the limitations of phonetic writing and the irreducibility of certain marks to their phonetic rendering. This silent mark exemplifies how writing exceeds speech, how the graphic element cannot be fully captured in the phonic. The play between the visible and the invisible, the audible and the inaudible in différance demonstrates the impossibility of a pure, self-present meaning that would transcend the play of signifiers. Différance operates through a double movement of spatial differentiation and temporal deferral. Spatially, each element in a system is what it is only by virtue of its differences from other elements—it has no positive identity in itself. Temporally, meaning is never fully present but always deferred, always caught in a movement of referral to other elements. This double movement means that no element can ever be simply present in itself; each element is constituted by the traces of other elements within it. The notion of the trace is crucial here. The trace is not a presence but rather the simulacrum of a presence that dislocates, displaces, and refers beyond itself. The trace has no place, for effacement belongs to its structure. The trace is not only the disappearance of origin; it means that the origin did not even disappear, that it was never constituted except reciprocally by a non-origin, the trace, which thus becomes the origin of the origin. This paradoxical formulation challenges the very notion of an absolute beginning or foundation. The play of différance and the trace disrupts the traditional metaphysical oppositions that have structured Western thought: presence/absence, speech/writing, nature/culture, inside/outside. These oppositions are revealed not as natural divisions but as hierarchical constructions that privilege one term over the other. Deconstruction does not simply reverse these hierarchies but displaces the entire system of oppositions, showing how each term is already inhabited by its supposed opposite.
Chapter 4: The Supplement: Revealing Absence Within Presence
The concept of the supplement provides a powerful tool for understanding how logocentrism maintains itself while simultaneously undermining its own foundations. A supplement is an addition to something supposedly complete in itself, yet this addition reveals a lack or absence in what was thought to be complete. The supplement thus has a dual and contradictory character: it both adds to a presence and substitutes for an absence. This paradoxical logic operates throughout the metaphysical tradition, particularly in its treatment of writing as a supplement to speech. In the logocentric tradition, writing is conceived as an external supplement to speech, a technical aid that merely represents what is already fully present in the spoken word. Yet this supplementary status of writing reveals a lack within speech itself—if speech were truly self-sufficient, it would not need the supplement of writing. The very possibility of supplementation indicates that what is supposedly original and self-present (speech) is already marked by the absence and difference that it attempts to externalize in the supplement (writing). The economy of supplementarity thus reveals that what metaphysics posits as original, natural, or self-present is always already constituted through a process of supplementation. Nature is always already supplemented by culture, presence by absence, speech by writing. The supplement is not a positive thing, an entity or substance added to another; it is rather a possibility or necessity inscribed within the supposedly original or natural term. This logic of supplementarity extends beyond the specific relationship between speech and writing to characterize the structure of signification in general. All signification operates through a supplementary logic in which each sign supplements another in an endless chain of referral. There is no transcendental signified that would arrest this movement, no meaning that would be present in itself without the supplementary play of signifiers. The concept of supplementarity thus challenges the metaphysical desire for an origin, a foundation, or a center that would ground the play of differences. It reveals that what metaphysics posits as original or foundational is always already caught up in a differential network, always already constituted through its relations to what it is not. The supplement is not a secondary or derivative phenomenon but is constitutive of what it supplements.
Chapter 5: The Trace: Undermining the Possibility of Pure Origins
The trace designates the impossibility of a sign being fully present to itself, the necessary reference to what is other than itself that constitutes any element in a signifying system. Unlike traditional philosophical concepts, the trace cannot be defined through opposition to something else. It precedes and produces the very possibility of opposition. It is neither present nor absent, neither sensible nor intelligible in the traditional sense. It names the differential movement that produces these oppositions while exceeding them. This originary trace undermines the notion of origin that has guided Western thought. If every element in a system is constituted by its differences from other elements, then there can be no pure origin, no point of absolute beginning. What we call origins are always already caught in a network of differences, traces of other elements. The origin is always already divided from itself, marked by the trace of what it is not. This insight challenges not only specific philosophical doctrines but the very framework within which philosophy has traditionally operated. The trace transforms our understanding of time and history. The linear, progressive time of traditional historiography presupposes a series of present moments. The trace reveals that each "present" is already divided, marked by traces of past and future. History cannot be understood as the unfolding of presence but must be reconceived as the play of differences that never resolves into full presence. The search for origins—whether of language, society, or meaning—must give way to an analysis of the differential movements that make the very concept of origin possible. This rethinking of origin and identity has profound implications for how we understand subjectivity. The self-present subject of traditional metaphysics—from Descartes' cogito to Husserl's transcendental ego—is revealed as an effect of the trace rather than its source. Consciousness does not precede language but is constituted through the same differential movements that structure language. The subject is not the origin of meaning but is itself an effect produced within the play of differences. The trace also disrupts the metaphysical opposition between presence and absence. It is neither simply present nor simply absent but rather the mark of an absence within presence, the indication that what appears as self-identical is already divided from within. This structure precedes and makes possible the conventional distinction between presence and absence. The trace thus reveals that presence is never pure or full but always already inhabited by absence, by the trace of what it is not. The concept of the trace extends beyond language to all systems of signification. It characterizes not only linguistic signs but all forms of meaning and experience. The trace reveals that meaning emerges not through the presence of self-identical elements but through the differential relations among elements that have no positive identity in themselves. This insight transforms our understanding not only of language but of all structures traditionally conceived in terms of presence, origin, and foundation.
Chapter 6: Beyond Binary Oppositions: Deconstructing Metaphysical Categories
The critique of logocentrism ultimately leads beyond the binary oppositions that have structured Western metaphysics. The opposition between nature and culture, like those between speech and writing, presence and absence, has traditionally been conceived as a hierarchical relationship in which one term is privileged as original and the other as derivative. Yet this critique reveals that such oppositions are neither natural nor stable but are produced through complex processes of differentiation and exclusion. The nature/culture opposition has played a particularly important role in Western thought, organizing not only philosophical discourse but also anthropological, political, and ethical theories. Nature is typically conceived as the realm of the given, the spontaneous, and the universal, while culture represents the constructed, the artificial, and the particular. This opposition underlies many other conceptual distinctions, including those between innate and acquired characteristics, biological and social determinants, and universal and particular values. Yet this neat opposition breaks down under scrutiny. What we call nature is never accessible to us outside of cultural frameworks and linguistic articulations. Our very concept of nature is a cultural product, shaped by historical and social factors. Conversely, culture is not simply imposed upon a passive natural substrate but emerges from natural processes and remains embedded in them. The boundary between nature and culture thus proves to be porous and unstable, a product of conceptual distinctions rather than an objective division in reality. This deconstruction of binary oppositions has significant implications for how we understand human language and society. Language can no longer be divided into natural and cultural components, with speech assigned to nature and writing to culture. Both speech and writing emerge from a more complex process that precedes and exceeds this binary opposition. Similarly, society cannot be understood through a simple narrative of progress or decline from a natural to a cultural state. The social is neither a corruption of natural innocence nor a transcendence of natural limitations, but a complex field of relations that transforms what we understand as both natural and cultural. Moving beyond binary oppositions does not mean synthesizing them into a higher unity or finding a middle ground between them. Rather, it involves recognizing the irreducible complexity that precedes and exceeds such oppositions. This recognition opens new possibilities for thinking difference outside the hierarchical structure of binary opposition. It allows us to conceive of differences that are neither oppositional nor dialectical, neither contradictory nor complementary, but differential in a more radical sense.
Chapter 7: Implications for Language, Meaning and Subjectivity
The deconstruction of logocentrism fundamentally transforms our understanding of language, meaning, and subjectivity. If différance precedes and makes possible all conceptual oppositions, then language cannot be understood as a system of representation that stands over against a pre-linguistic reality. Language does not simply represent a world that exists independently of it but actively constitutes our experience of that world. This does not mean that there is nothing outside language, but rather that what lies outside language is never accessible to us in its pure presence, unmediated by linguistic articulation. This transformation extends to our understanding of meaning itself. Meaning is not a presence to be recovered but an effect produced within the play of differences. It emerges not through the presence of self-identical elements but through the differential relations among elements that have no positive identity in themselves. Meaning is thus never fully present, never completely determined, but always caught in a movement of deferral and differentiation. This does not imply that meaning is arbitrary or subjective, but rather that it is constituted through structural relations rather than through reference to transcendental signifieds. The subject, traditionally conceived as the origin of meaning and the site of self-presence, is similarly transformed. The subject is not a pre-linguistic entity that subsequently enters into language but is itself constituted through linguistic and social processes. The "I" that speaks or writes is not the origin of language but an effect produced within language. This does not mean that the subject is a mere illusion or that agency is impossible, but rather that subjectivity must be reconceived in terms of différance rather than presence. This reconceptualization has profound implications for ethics and politics. If identity is always constituted through difference, if presence is always marked by absence, then political projects based on assertions of pure identity or presence require fundamental rethinking. Similarly, ethical frameworks that appeal to natural law or transcendental values must confront the instability of the nature/culture opposition. The critique of logocentrism thus opens new possibilities for ethical and political thought that acknowledge the irreducible complexity of human existence. The implications extend to our understanding of history and temporality. If the present is never fully present to itself but always already divided by the trace, then history cannot be conceived as a linear progression of present moments. The past is not simply what is no longer present, nor is the future simply what is not yet present. Rather, past and future are inscribed within the present as traces, as the differential movement that constitutes the present as such. This reconceptualization challenges teleological narratives of historical progress and opens new ways of thinking about historical time. The transformation of our understanding of language, meaning, and subjectivity does not simply negate traditional concepts but displaces them, showing how they are effects produced within the play of différance rather than foundational principles. This displacement does not lead to relativism or nihilism but to a more rigorous understanding of how meaning and value emerge within differential structures. It challenges us to think difference differently, not as the opposition between self-identical terms but as the differential play that constitutes the possibility of identity itself.
Summary
The deconstruction of the metaphysics of presence reveals how Western thought has been structured by a privileging of speech over writing that reflects deeper commitments to presence, identity, and origin. By examining this privileging across philosophical texts, we uncover not merely a theoretical preference but a fundamental structure that shapes Western self-understanding and its relation to cultural others. The concepts of différance, trace, and supplement provide tools for thinking beyond the constraints of metaphysical oppositions. They reveal how presence is always already inhabited by absence, identity by difference, immediacy by mediation. This transformation in our understanding of language and meaning has profound implications for how we conceive of subjectivity, ethics, politics, and history. If the subject is constituted through the same differential movements that structure language, then we must reconsider political projects based on assertions of pure identity or presence. If nature and culture are not opposed but intricately intertwined, then ethical frameworks that appeal to either natural law or cultural construction require fundamental rethinking. The critique of logocentrism thus opens new possibilities for thought and action that acknowledge the irreducible complexity of human existence while refusing both the nostalgia for lost presence and the celebration of endless fragmentation. It challenges us to inhabit the tensions and paradoxes of language and meaning without seeking to resolve them into a higher unity or abandoning the quest for understanding altogether.
Best Quote
“Il n'y a pas de hors-texte.” ― Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology
Review Summary
Strengths: The review highlights the concept of deconstruction as a means of achieving freedom from oppressive tropes. It emphasizes the potential of deconstruction to enable wise and decisive action against these constraints. The review also appreciates the book's focus on written tropes and its availability as a key study by Derrida. Weaknesses: Not explicitly mentioned. Overall Sentiment: Enthusiastic Key Takeaway: The review underscores the importance of deconstruction in liberating the mind from the pervasive and often harmful influence of various tropes, particularly political ones. It suggests that deconstruction can help individuals discern the true motives behind actions and avoid being misled by deceptive narratives.
Trending Books
Download PDF & EPUB
To save this Black List summary for later, download the free PDF and EPUB. You can print it out, or read offline at your convenience.

Of Grammatology
By Jacques Derrida