Home/Nonfiction/Being and Nothingness
Loading...
Being and Nothingness cover

Being and Nothingness

A Phenomenological Essay on Ontology

4.0 (33,773 ratings)
23 minutes read | Text | 9 key ideas
In the labyrinth of human consciousness, Jean-Paul Sartre’s "Being and Nothingness" invites readers to confront the raw, unfiltered essence of existence. Written in the tumultuous era of 1943, this philosophical titan unravels the tensions between freedom and determinism, and the dance of objectivity with subjectivity. Sartre challenges us to peer into the void, questioning the very fabric of our choices and identities. With existential psychoanalysis as its backbone, this groundbreaking work peels back the layers of what it means to truly "be." It’s a cerebral exploration that demands introspection, poised to ignite the minds of those willing to grapple with life's profound complexities.

Categories

Nonfiction, Psychology, Philosophy, Classics, Unfinished, Literature, Theory, 20th Century, France, French Literature

Content Type

Book

Binding

Paperback

Year

1966

Publisher

Washington Square Press

Language

English

ASIN

0671496069

ISBN

0671496069

ISBN13

9780671496067

File Download

PDF | EPUB

Being and Nothingness Plot Summary

Introduction

What does it mean to exist as a conscious being in a world of objects? This fundamental question has perplexed philosophers throughout history, yet traditional approaches have often created artificial divisions between subject and object, mind and matter, consciousness and world. Existential phenomenology offers a radical alternative by examining human existence not as a fixed essence but as a dynamic process of becoming, where consciousness exists in perpetual tension with the material world. At its core, this philosophical framework explores the unique nature of human consciousness as fundamentally different from the being of objects. While objects simply are what they are, human consciousness exists as a form of nothingness—a perpetual self-transcendence that never coincides with itself. Through this lens, we can understand the ontological structure of freedom, the nature of self-deception, the complex dynamics of interpersonal relations, and the lived experience of embodiment. Rather than abstract theoretical constructs, these insights illuminate the very fabric of our everyday existence, revealing how we navigate the fundamental tensions between freedom and facticity, authenticity and bad faith, selfhood and otherness.

Chapter 1: The Ontological Structure of Consciousness

Consciousness represents a unique form of being that differs fundamentally from the existence of objects in the world. While objects exist in a mode of complete self-identity—a rock simply is what it is, without distance from itself—consciousness exists as a perpetual escape from self-coincidence. This peculiar structure means that human consciousness is never fully identical with itself; it always exists at a distance from itself, in a state of self-relation that introduces nothingness into the heart of being. The essential characteristic of consciousness is intentionality—consciousness is always consciousness of something. When I perceive a tree, my consciousness is not a container holding an image of the tree; rather, my consciousness is precisely this relation to the tree as something distinct from me. This directedness toward objects means consciousness cannot be contained within itself like an object in a box. It exists as a kind of "hole in being," defined by what it is not rather than by what it is. This ontological structure creates a fundamental distinction between two modes of being: being-in-itself (the mode of objects) and being-for-itself (the mode of consciousness). The in-itself is characterized by fullness, identity, and contingency—it simply is what it is. The for-itself, by contrast, is characterized by lack, self-transcendence, and nothingness. Human reality exists in the tension between these two modes, perpetually seeking to become what it is not—a futile project of trying to become both in-itself and for-itself simultaneously. The structure of consciousness explains our peculiar relationship to time. Unlike objects that simply exist in the present, human reality temporalizes itself by simultaneously existing its past (as facticity), its present (as presence to the world), and its future (as possibility). I am my past in the mode of not-being it—it is behind me as what I was, yet I cannot coincide with it. I am my future in the mode of possibility—what I project myself to be but am not yet. This temporal dispersion reveals consciousness as fundamentally dynamic, never achieving the static self-identity of objects. Consider how this manifests in everyday experience: when you make a promise, you project a future self who will fulfill that promise, yet this future self exists only as possibility, not as determined reality. When you feel regret, you confront your past as something that is irrevocably you, yet which you can no longer change or coincide with. These experiences reveal the fundamental structure of consciousness as a being that is what it is not and is not what it is—a paradoxical formulation that captures the unique ontology of human existence.

Chapter 2: Nothingness and the Origin of Negation

Nothingness is not merely the absence of being but an active force that enters the world through human consciousness. Unlike traditional metaphysics that treats nothingness as a logical concept or as the opposite of being, existential philosophy recognizes nothingness as something that "happens" to being through human reality. This nothingness is not self-generated; it requires a being through which nothingness comes to being—the being-for-itself of human consciousness. The for-itself exists as a perpetual nihilation of the in-itself, creating a separation between itself and the world, between itself and its past, between itself and its future possibilities. This separation is not a physical distance but an ontological one—a nothingness that allows consciousness to stand back from being and question it. When I contemplate a glass on the table, my consciousness is not the glass, nor is it a container holding an image of the glass. Rather, consciousness is precisely this relation to the glass as something that consciousness is not. This nihilating power manifests in distinctly human activities that reveal the presence of nothingness in our everyday lives. Questioning presupposes nothingness—when I ask "Is there a chair in the room?" I stand in a position of not-knowing, creating a possibility of negative response. Destruction can only be conceived by a being that can apprehend what is no longer there—when we say "the city was destroyed," we are comparing present nothingness with a previous fullness that we hold in mind. Even imagination requires this nihilating power—to imagine Paris is to hold the real world at a distance and posit an unreal Paris. The most profound expression of this nothingness lies in human freedom. Because consciousness is not bound by causal determinism like objects in the world, it can nihilate the given situation and project itself toward possibilities. When faced with a precipice, I experience anxiety not merely from the possibility of falling but from the possibility that I might throw myself off. This anxiety reveals that nothing prevents me from doing so—no instinct, no causal determination, no past decision. I am radically free precisely because nothingness separates me from my past and my future self. Consider how we experience absence in everyday life. When I enter a café looking for my friend Pierre and discover "he is not there," this absence is not simply given in the world like the tables and chairs. Rather, my consciousness actively nihilates the café, organizing it as a background against which Pierre's absence stands out as a meaningful phenomenon. This ability to experience absence—to see what is not there—reveals the nihilating power of consciousness that introduces nothingness into the world. Only a being that can transcend the mere positivity of what is can introduce the "not" into the world.

Chapter 3: Freedom, Choice and Responsibility

Freedom, in existential philosophy, is not a property that humans possess but the very mode of human existence. To be conscious is to be free in the sense that consciousness always exists as a separation from what it is—as the ability to transcend given conditions toward possibilities. This freedom is not a freedom of achievement (being able to accomplish whatever we desire) but a freedom of choice in how we relate to our situation. We are "condemned to freedom," forced to choose ourselves without any predetermined guidelines. This radical freedom manifests in the structure of human action. When I act, I do not simply respond to causal forces but project myself toward possibilities that I choose. Even in highly constrained situations, I retain the freedom to determine what these constraints mean for me. A prisoner facing a long sentence still chooses how to live within those walls—whether to pursue education, form relationships, or surrender to despair. The physical limitations do not eliminate freedom but provide the concrete situation within which freedom must be exercised. With this inescapable freedom comes an equally inescapable responsibility. Since I am not determined by external causes or internal drives, I am responsible for what I make of myself and my situation. This responsibility extends even to aspects of my existence that I did not choose. I did not choose my historical era, my early upbringing, or my natural talents, yet I am responsible for what I do with these givens—how I incorporate them into my ongoing project of self-creation. Even when I claim to be following orders or social norms, I am choosing to recognize the authority of those orders or norms. The weight of this responsibility produces what existentialists call "anguish"—the vertigo of recognizing that nothing determines our choices except our own choosing. When facing a significant life decision, the anxiety we feel stems not primarily from the potential consequences but from the realization that nothing—no rule, authority, or natural order—can make the choice for us. We alone must decide, and in deciding, we define not only what we will do but who we will become. Consider how this plays out in concrete ethical dilemmas. When faced with competing obligations—say, between caring for an ill parent and pursuing a career opportunity abroad—no external standard can determine the "right" choice. The existentialist recognizes that whichever choice they make creates the hierarchy of values by which the choice can be judged. If I choose to stay with my parent, I affirm through this choice that family obligations take precedence over career advancement—not because this hierarchy existed before my choice, but because my choice establishes it.

Chapter 4: Bad Faith and Self-Deception

Bad faith represents a peculiar form of self-deception through which consciousness attempts to escape the anguish of freedom and responsibility. Unlike ordinary lying, which presupposes a clear distinction between deceiver and deceived, bad faith involves consciousness lying to itself—a paradoxical project that requires consciousness to be both aware and unaware of the same truth simultaneously. This self-deception is possible because consciousness is not a fixed entity but a dynamic relation to itself, always at a distance from itself. Bad faith typically manifests in two complementary forms: either reducing oneself to facticity (treating oneself as a mere thing determined by nature, history, or social roles) or dissolving oneself into pure transcendence (denying one's concrete situation and limitations). The waiter who performs his role with exaggerated precision, moving like a mechanical doll, exemplifies the first form—he pretends to be a waiter in the way that an inkwell is an inkwell, as if his role defined his being completely. Conversely, the woman who leaves her hand in her companion's grasp while mentally detaching herself from the situation exemplifies the second form—she pretends that her body is not herself, that she can float free of her concrete embodiment. These strategies of bad faith attempt to resolve the fundamental tension of human reality: that we are beings who are what we are not (our possibilities) and are not what we are (our facticity). We cannot coincide with ourselves either as pure facticity or as pure transcendence, yet bad faith pretends that such coincidence is possible. The man who says "I am a homosexual" as if this defined his being completely and the man who says "I am not a homosexual" while acknowledging homosexual behavior both engage in bad faith—one by identifying completely with his past actions, the other by detaching completely from them. What makes bad faith particularly fascinating is that it cannot be understood as simple lying. When I lie to someone else, I know the truth I'm concealing. But in bad faith, I must both know and not know the truth simultaneously. I must be aware of my freedom in order to flee from it, yet this awareness must remain non-thetic (not explicitly formulated) to maintain the deception. This paradoxical structure reveals consciousness as fundamentally non-coincident with itself—always at a distance from itself. Consider how bad faith operates in everyday life: the person who claims "I can't help being late; it's just how I am" treats a pattern of choices as a fixed essence, while the person who makes promises without considering their concrete ability to fulfill them treats themselves as pure possibility unconstrained by situation. Both evade the responsibility that comes from recognizing oneself as a freedom engaged in a concrete situation, as simultaneously facticity and transcendence. These patterns reveal our complex relationship with our own freedom—simultaneously cherishing it and fleeing from the responsibility it entails.

Chapter 5: Being-for-Others and Intersubjectivity

The existence of other conscious beings introduces a profound dimension to human existence that cannot be reduced to the relation between consciousness and objects. The Other is not simply another object in my world but another subjectivity that experiences me as an object in their world. This fundamental relation cannot be derived from solitary consciousness but must be understood as an irreducible structure of human existence. Through the Other, I discover aspects of myself that escape my direct experience—my appearance, my character as perceived externally, my social identity. The paradigmatic experience of the Other is "the look." When I realize someone is watching me—perhaps while I'm engaged in something embarrassing like peering through a keyhole—I suddenly experience myself as visible from the outside. This visibility is not merely physical but ontological: under the Other's gaze, I become an object with fixed characteristics rather than a free transcendence. My possibilities no longer radiate from me into the world but are contained and limited by the Other's freedom. This experience of being seen fundamentally transforms my relation to myself and to the world. This relation to the Other creates a fundamental conflict at the heart of human relations. As a for-itself, I strive to maintain my freedom and subjectivity while simultaneously needing the Other's recognition to confirm aspects of my being that I cannot access directly. Yet the Other's freedom threatens to reduce me to an object, just as my freedom threatens to objectify the Other. This creates a dialectical struggle in which each consciousness attempts to assert its freedom while capturing the other's. This conflict manifests in various concrete attitudes toward others—love, indifference, desire, hate—each representing a different strategy for negotiating this fundamental tension. The body plays a crucial role in this intersubjective realm. I exist my body primarily as lived experience—as the center of action and perception through which I engage with the world. But through the Other's look, my body becomes also an object for others, with characteristics that escape my immediate experience. This duality of the body—as both lived from within and observed from without—creates another dimension of alienation in human existence. I cannot experience my body as others see it, yet this external dimension is an inescapable aspect of my being. Consider how this intersubjective structure shapes everyday social interactions. When giving a public speech, I am acutely aware of myself as visible, as exposed to evaluations I cannot control. This awareness is not an inference but a direct experience of my being-for-others. Similarly, shame reveals the Other's presence even when no empirical other is physically present—I can feel ashamed when alone because the dimension of being-for-others has been internalized as a structural feature of my existence. These experiences reveal that intersubjectivity is not a contingent fact about human existence but constitutive of it.

Chapter 6: Temporality and the Structure of Human Action

Time is not merely a container in which human existence unfolds; rather, temporality constitutes the very structure of consciousness itself. Unlike physical objects that exist wholly in the present moment, human consciousness exists by temporalizing itself—by simultaneously extending into past, present, and future. This temporal structure is not imposed from outside but emerges from the very nature of consciousness as a self-relating process that never coincides with itself. The past exists for consciousness not as a collection of memories or mental images but as the facticity that I am and must continue to be. My past is not separate from me—I am my past, though in the mode of "having to be what I am not." For example, a person who has committed a crime cannot simply discard this act as belonging to a separate time; they must continue to be this past action while simultaneously not being reduced to it. This explains why we feel responsible for our past actions even while recognizing we are no longer exactly the person who performed them. The present moment of consciousness is characterized by presence—not as a static "now-point" but as an active engagement with the world. When I am absorbed in a task like reading or playing tennis, I am present to the world in a way that transcends the instantaneous moment. This presence is not a solid state but a form of absence—I am present precisely by not coinciding with myself, by projecting beyond my current state toward possibilities. The present is thus paradoxically defined by what it is not: it is not the past (which I was) and not the future (which I will be). The future dimension reveals consciousness as possibility and project. Unlike the deterministic future of physical events, human futurity is characterized by openness and uncertainty. When I project myself toward the future—planning a career, anticipating a meeting, or simply reaching for a glass of water—I exist in relation to possibilities that are not yet real but which give meaning to my present actions. The future is not simply what will happen but what I am making happen through my current projects and commitments. This temporal structure fundamentally shapes human action. When I act, I do not simply respond to causal forces but project myself toward possibilities in light of an end I have chosen. My motives gain their force not as psychological causes but as aspects of the project through which I define myself. Consider how a mountain climber experiences fatigue: the physical sensations become meaningful as "exhaustion" only in relation to the project of reaching the summit. The same physical state might be experienced differently within a different project. This reveals that action cannot be understood through causal models but must be interpreted in terms of the temporal structure of consciousness as it projects itself toward freely chosen ends.

Chapter 7: The Body as Lived Experience

The body occupies a unique position in human existence, representing neither a mere physical object nor a separate entity that consciousness "inhabits." Rather, the body exists in three distinct ontological dimensions: the body-for-itself (as lived experience), the body-for-others (as seen from outside), and the body-for-itself-for-others (as I experience my objectification by others). These dimensions reveal how embodiment fundamentally shapes our engagement with the world and with others. As body-for-itself, we do not "have" a body but rather exist our body as the viewpoint from which we perceive and act upon the world. This lived body is not an object of knowledge but the very condition of all knowledge. When I reach for a glass, I do not first locate my hand as an object in space and then calculate its trajectory; rather, I live my hand directly as a reaching-toward-the-glass. The body-for-itself is invisible precisely because it is that through which we see; it is the center of reference that organizes our perceptual field but which cannot itself be perceived as an object within that field. The body manifests as our facticity—our necessary contingency as beings situated in the world. It represents both the instrument of our freedom and its limitation. Through my body, I engage with possibilities in the world, yet my bodily capacities also constrain what possibilities are available to me. This ambiguous status explains why we often experience our bodies as both intimately ours and strangely alien, particularly in experiences of pain, fatigue, or illness where the body's resistance to our projects becomes explicit. The body-for-others reveals another dimension of embodiment. Through the Other's look, my body becomes an object with characteristics that escape my direct experience. I cannot see my own face as others see it, yet this face constitutes an essential aspect of my being in the social world. This objectification is not merely a psychological experience but an ontological structure—the Other's perception reveals a dimension of my being that I cannot access directly. This creates a fundamental alienation: part of what I am exists beyond my reach, in the consciousness of others. Consider how we experience physical pain. When my hand hurts, this pain is not a sensation "in" my hand that consciousness then perceives. Rather, consciousness exists this pain directly as a modification of its relation to the world. The painful hand reorganizes my entire perceptual field—objects appear as "to be handled carefully" or "to be avoided," and my projects are reconfigured around this pain. The pain is neither purely physical nor purely mental but reveals the body as lived consciousness engaged with the world.

Summary

Existential phenomenology reveals that human existence is fundamentally characterized by a dynamic tension between freedom and facticity, where consciousness (being-for-itself) perpetually transcends itself toward possibilities while never achieving the self-coincidence of objects (being-in-itself). This framework transforms our understanding of human experience by showing how we are simultaneously defined by radical freedom and inescapable responsibility. The profound insight at the heart of this philosophy is that existence precedes essence—we have no predetermined nature but must create ourselves through our choices in a world where no absolute values or meanings exist prior to our projects. Through the dialectical interplay between being and nothingness, we discover that meaning emerges neither from objective structures in the world nor from subjective projection, but from the engaged encounter between human freedom and concrete situations. This perspective offers neither comfort nor despair, but rather an invitation to authentic living—to embrace the ambiguity of human existence by acknowledging both our absolute freedom and our situated facticity, both our solitude as individual consciousnesses and our inescapable entanglement with others in a shared world.

Best Quote

“It is therefore senseless to think of complaining since nothing foreign has decided what we feel, what we live, or what we are.” ― Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness

Review Summary

Strengths: The review highlights the foundational nature of Sartre's "Being and Nothingness" in existential philosophy, emphasizing its exploration of individual existence and free will. It notes Sartre's philosophical development influenced by Heidegger's "Being and Time," showcasing the book's intellectual depth and historical context. Weaknesses: Not explicitly mentioned. Overall Sentiment: The review conveys a respectful and appreciative sentiment towards Sartre's work, recognizing its significance in 20th-century philosophy and its complex exploration of existential themes. Key Takeaway: "Being and Nothingness" is a seminal work in existential philosophy, deeply influenced by Heidegger, that argues for the primacy of existence over essence and affirms the existence of free will, marking a pivotal point in philosophical thought.

About Author

Loading...
Jean-Paul Sartre Avatar

Jean-Paul Sartre

Read more

Download PDF & EPUB

To save this Black List summary for later, download the free PDF and EPUB. You can print it out, or read offline at your convenience.

Book Cover

Being and Nothingness

By Jean-Paul Sartre

0:00/0:00

Build Your Library

Select titles that spark your interest. We'll find bite-sized summaries you'll love.